The problem with group selection is not so much that it's wrong, but that it causes confusion among its practitioners. For decades group selection advocates held out hope that their theory would make novel predictions. In the last decade, this hope has mostly collapsed and most now recognize that group selection and kin selection are broadly equivalent. It is a matter of different accounting techniques, so to speak.
The main problem is that we know that kin selection is strongest between close relatives. Group selection advocates often want to apply the theories to whole tribes and to warfare. This sort of group selection isn't equivalent to kin selection - and, for the most part, it doesn't actually work.
What is left of this whole debate? Not too much. There's some noise surrounding Hamilton's inclusive fitness concept, but this is mostly coming from Martin Nowak and friends - and his papers have been met with ridicule. At this stage, most of the facts seem to be in and the group selection controversy resembles a mopping up operation.
4. Group selection debate - Stuart West from LERN: London Evolution on Vimeo.
It isn't hard to think of reasons for this, but many of of those reasons invoke the idea of prospective kin - unborn children.
Most children have a probability of becoming an ancestor - and it is possible to extend this idea to children that haven't been born - and to children that haven't been even conceived.
Pretty standard kin selection models can thus be applied to courtship behaviour, bower construction, nuptual gifts - and so forth. These are cases where cooperative behaviour without relatedness occurs. In fact, there is relatedness - relatedness to unborn children.
That paper was mostly smacked down by critics because of its delusional depiction of kin selection, but few bothered to criticize its model of the evolution of eusociality. Now, David Queller's gone through the model, and the results are not too pretty.
They had a modeling strategy that should work and should be fine, but they weren’t careful enough when they made claims about their models’ novel results...David Queller is quoted as saying.
From the abstract of the article:
The claim of these authors was bolstered by a new model of the evolution of eusociality with novel conclusions that appeared to overturn some major results from inclusive fitness. Here we report an expanded examination of this kind of model for the evolution of eusociality and show that all three of its apparently novel conclusions are essentially false. Contrary to their claims, genetic relatedness is important and causal, workers are agents that can evolve to be in conflict with the queen, and eusociality is not so difficult to evolve. The misleading conclusions all resulted not from incorrect math but from overgeneralizing from narrow assumptions or parameter values. For example, all of their models implicitly assumed high relatedness, but modifying the model to allow lower relatedness shows that relatedness is essential and causal in the evolution of eusociality. Their modeling strategy, properly applied, actually confirms major insights of inclusive fitness studies of kin selection. This broad agreement of different models shows that social evolution theory, rather than being in turmoil, is supported by multiple theoretical approaches. It also suggests that extensive prior work using inclusive fitness, from microbial interactions to human evolution, should be considered robust unless shown otherwise.Queller's paper certainly makes entertaining reading. However I can't help thinking that it takes the Nowak/Tarnita/Wilson paper too seriously. The most obvious response to that paper is, I think, ridicule. Jon Wilkins hit roughly the right note with Important Harvard Scientists Attack Kin Selection.
News coverage:
Nowak and Allen reply in Inclusive Fitness Theorizing Invokes Phenomena That Are Not Relevant for the Evolution of Eusociality
Liao, Rong and Queller reply: Some Agreement on Kin Selection and Eusociality?
Nowak's papers on the topic are here.
Inclusive fitness turns out to be a phantom measure that cannot be obtained....and...
Inclusive fitness theory is neither useful nor necessary to explain the evolution of eusociality or other phenomena.Further, the second quote was mirrored by Google at the top of its search results for "inclusive fitness" - as though it was a definition of the term! You might still be able to see this for yourself here.
Low levels of machine intelligence can cause this sort of problem, it seems.
However, it seems that David Sloane Wilson still has doubts about this. He doesn't see how to apply kin selection in some cases - and he's publicly asking for help. As far as I can see, David has nothing. One of his three examples is cultural group selection. I replied here.
I'm not sure how much help David will get from other kin selection enthusiasts. Most have been unimpressed with David's attempts to rechristen and take credit for a well-established existing theory. Group selection has a long association with junk science. Kin selection depends on close relatedness to produce adaptations. If you emphasize group membership instead of close relatedness - you include a bunch of cases where there's no close relatedness, and adaptations are not produced. Group selection was pushed by kin selection into the scientific fringes - where it focused on cases not obviously explicable by kin selection - which were mostly cases where the theory didn't actually work. In short, group selection is kin selection's evil twin.
David engages in a bit of a straw man attack on kin selection in his article. He focuses on Hamilton's rule. Hamilton's rule is one of the findings by kin selection theorists - but it isn't the same thing as kin selection. Here's how Hamilton explained the topic:
The existence of altruism in nature can be explained by thinking about the replication of genes. We need to descend to the level of the gene, rather than the individual, in order to see that the gene exists surrounded by copies of identical genes that exist in all its relatives - in particular in its close relatives, its siblings, who have a half chance of carrying a copy of that particular gene, its offspring, which also have a half chance, parents: a half-chance, cousins: one eighth, etc. Seeing this swarm of genes that exists around a particular one, we can then ask what is the behavior caused by this gene that is most likely to cause the propagation of this set of copies in the relatives around it.That is more like kin selection in a nutshell. Of course, these days, we have to clarify that it's the evolutionary gene that we mean here. Hamilton's rule is the product of kin selection and a bunch of assumptions.